Barbara J. Fields' engaging and very important book Racecraft: my draft review.
The
book can be thought of as composed of several key elements. The
obvious starting point is the idea of racecraft as such, but this
part has two distinct aspects.
In
the Introduction and the first two chapters, we see the emergence of
the notion of racecraft itself, as opposed to race, and also
racialization. Racecraft begins as a critique of the notion of
“race” as something one can have or be, which allows the authors
to challenge notions such as “being multiracial” or the idea that
there is a biological notion of race which might be grasped through
genetics. This is extremely important politically in the present
because a biological notion of race has re-emerged into
respectability not only among reactionaries, but in mainstream
science and so-called liberal discourse through identity, including
intersectionality. The use of racecraft to critique this
re-emergence of race, which serves to obscure that race itself is
nothing more than a by-product of racism, of a certain kind of
relationship of power, or as Fields says,
“Starting
from “ethnoracial mixture” leads to the great evasion of American
historical literature, as of American history itself: the
substitution of “race” for “racism.” That substitution, as I
have written elsewhere, “transforms the act of a subject into an
attribute of the object.”4 Disguised as race, racism
becomes something Afro-Americans are, rather than something racists
do.”
Fields,
Barbara J.. Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life (pp.
96-97). Verso Books. Kindle Edition.
This
point is fundamental to her analysis, but I want to trouble it right
from the start. Let us say that we approach nation, class, or gender
in the same way. Would we then say that disguised as class, classes
becomes something workers are, rather than something classists do?
Disguised as nations, nationalism becomes something Americans are,
rather than something nationalists do? Disguised as sex, sexism
becomes something women are, rather than something sexists do?
Posed
this way, we have two choices. The first choice is to say that, yes,
in fact, all social forms are products of a definite structured
social practicei,
and thus class, gender, race, sexuality, nation are all merely modes
of expression or modes of existence of some fundamental social
relation, and thus not only race but also gender, class, nation and
so on are constituted by this society rather than being per se
constituting.ii
One would then further have to reckon that race is not merely a
product of the activity of racists or racialists, but is a
determinate social category of this society as much as class, nation,
gender, etc. That necessarily entails that as much as race, we have
to propose that nation, class, gender, etc. do not exist outside of
this form of society and would cease to exist if we managed to get
rid of this society.iii
The
other option is the one that Fields chooses quite explicitly, that
race is distinctly, though maybe not uniquely, not like class or
nation or products of material production.iv
For example, race doesn’t exist in the same way that the Brooklyn
Bridge and nations do. Not only that, but those who refer to “race”
use it as “a euphemism for slavery, disfranchisement, segregation,
lynching, mass murder, and related historical atrocities; or as
unintentionally belittling shorthand for “persons of African
descent and anything pertaining to them.” Fields, Barbara J..
Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life (p. 100). Verso
Books. Kindle Edition. The footnote following this includes David
Roediger’s Wages of Whiteness and Race and Reunion
by David Blight, books
one would be hard pressed to say treat race as a euphemism and a
belittling shorthand for Afro-Americans, lumping them in over the
next few pages with defenders of cab drivers not stopping for
African-Americans, promoters of “Black English” and teachers of
tolerance in place of equality, a move that seems to seek to deride
and defame rather than to reason.
Importantly for my point, Fields argues that “what they are
unknowingly searching for is a neutral-sounding word with racism
hidden inside, which is what “race” is.” Fields, Barbara J..
Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life (p. 102). Verso
Books. Kindle Edition. But then “nation” and “class” (and
maybe gender and sexuality?) are not inherently “neutral-sounding”
words with oppression and domination hidden inside.
For
this to not play out in this way, somehow class, nation and gender
would have to be something fundamentally different from race, somehow
not merely the mystification of oppression
Racecraft
is more than this alone, however, as it also entails a theory of the
production of racism and races.v
Chapters 3 and 4 in particular take up this idea of how racism and
race come to be in the American context as a product not merely of
slavery, but of a specific contradiction of the endorsement of
slavery by a radically democratic society that has otherwise
propounded the natural and inherently universal ‘Rights of Man’.
This analysis seems to provide a ground for the production of racism
and race and the necessary mystification of racecraft that turns
racism into race in order to make racism, that is a very specific
kind of unequal relation of power and oppression, disappear into
race.
However,
this linking of race specifically to the contradictions of the
American Revolution and American democracy with American slavery
invokes a kind of historical exceptionalism first claimed by the
American Communist Party, and it also essentializes democracy and
slavery as separate from capitalism. I would argue that for her
argument to work, in fact, slavery and democracy must float
independently of capitalism because otherwise we might wonder if
capitalism has not in fact produced racism and racecraft everywhere.
In fact, at one point she makes a very peculiar argument that if race
and racecraft were not specific to the American dilemma, how come no
one has made the argument for the racial production of the
Anglo-Irish relation. The 4th chapter was written in
1990, four years before the publication of Theodore Allen’s the
Invention of the White Race, so at the time no one could have
known that a book was being written that made exactly this
argument, but Racecraft was published almost two decades
after that and no mention is made in the footnotes of the presence of
exactly such an argument by what is, on all accounts, one of the most
widely discussed radical, class-based works on race since 1994. At
the same time, as I noted above, books published before Allen (The
Wages of Whiteness) and after (Race and Reunion) come in
for mention and aspersions, so it feel unlikely that Fields would not
be aware of Allen’s work, which was a much larger and more
sustained piece by Roediger’s own admission (c.f. Race, Class
and Marxism.)
The
commitment to American Exceptionalism is expressed in a reification
of all notions of “race” as “racism”.
“One
such peculiarity is the fact that, effectively, there can be only one
race, since the one-drop-of-blood or any-known-ancestry rule applies
only to African ancestry;17 indeed, the rule ceases to
function at all if applied to more than one type of ancestry. The
cosmetic applied to the resulting asymmetry and invidiousness is
“whiteness,” whose champions purport to discover
“racialization”—and therefore races—all over the shop. A
further sleight of hand defines race as identity so that “white”
also becomes a race.18” Fields, Barbara J.. Racecraft:
The Soul of Inequality in American Life (p. 102). Verso Books. Kindle
Edition.
Aside
from the manner in which this throws the idea of racism to the wind
for people of African descent in Latin America, for people of Mexican
or Chinese descent in the United States, and most notably for
Amer-Indian peoples all over the Western Hemisphere, it inherently
ties itself to a biological notion of race with the one-drop rule.
In the name of unmasking race as racism, a state of being with an
activity, all that happens is the recourse to an exceptionalism
associated with American peculiarity and cut-off from the broader
history of European colonialism and the internal relation between
race and nation in the history of capitalist society globally.
That
said, she nonetheless makes short work of “amalgamation” and
“multiracialism”, notions which takes as their foundation the
natural validity of “race”. However, one wonders if there is a
simple secular humanism underlying this point of view, one which is
sound as far as it goes “racism is wrong because it violates the
basic rights of human being and citizen” (Fields, Barbara J..
Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life (p. 107). Verso
Books. Kindle Edition), but which takes the abstract human being and
citizen i.e. the member of a duly constituted nation,
as its limit points.
Unfortunately,
despite her often excellent critique of identitarian notions of race, Fields lacks a
critique of identity as such and the way in which the production of
identity is endemic to capital as the dominant social form.
Therefore, she will counterpoise the idea of racial identity with
national identity, suggesting the latter is illegitimate and the
former is legitimate, in order to make the argument (in what is a
point easily overlooked in the 4th chapter) that
Afro-Americans did not historically see themselves as an identity or
a race, but as a nation. This argument strikes me as difficult to
defend, but more importantly, it echoed in my mind the position of
the American Communist Party on “the Black Belt Thesis” that
Afro-Americans constituted a nation. Having already had recourse to
this idea that Afro-Americans are not an identity or a race but a
nation, to the expression of American exceptionalism which regards
race and racism and racecraft to be uniquely American, and a
counterpoising of a false or ideological “race identity” with a
true or good “nation identity”, strongly reminded me of the
American Communist Party positions. However, nothing more than these
brief turns of phrase and logical juxtapositions are present in the
essays to justify any claim that Fields herself draws on the
positions of the CPUSA from the Third Period, when those ideas were
first formulated, or from the post-1948 return to that position
amidst the Cold War.
The
thesis of American exceptionalism at play in her works relies on a
very specific timeline. For example, she locates the production of
race as such as an outcome of the years leading up to and resulting
in the American Revolution and the subsequent continuation of slavery
after the revolution and the necessity of men holding to notions of
universal individual rights and humanity having to at the same time
make peace with and justify a system of slavery within their midst on
which they grew rich and which formed a key foundation of the
American republic.
This
requires her at one point [citation]
to claim that no such notions were forthcoming from England, which
had little problem in the early years of the colonies with forms of
indentured servitude for Englishmen and her claims rests to no small
degree on the historical timeline put forward by Edward Morgan, which
denies that there is any significant distinction between English
indentured servitude and African enslavement until late in the 17th
century. However, there is documented evidence that definite legal
distinctions between African slaves and English indentured servants
were already developed by the early 1650’s. In fact, Re
Negro John Punch (1640)
already began to make significant distinctions leading in the
direction of the racist production of racevi
and “Virginia was one of the first states to acknowledge slavery in
its laws, initially enacting such a law in 1661.36 The
following year, Virginia passed two laws that pertained solely to
women who were slaves or indentured servants and to their
illegitimate children. Women servants who produced children by their
masters could be punished by having to do two years of servitude with
the churchwardens after the expiration of the term with their
masters. The law reads, “that each woman servant gott with child by
her master shall after her time by indenture or custome is expired be
by the churchwardens of the parish where she lived when she was
brought to bed of such bastard, sold for two years. . . .”37”vii.
This undermines Morgan’s timeline, though not necessarily Theodore
Allen’s from Invention
of the White Race, which
argues that racism and race were produced as a conscious policy of
social control in response to acts of rebellion in which “Africans”
(having already been stripped of tribe and people by enslavement) and
Englishmen worked together, leading up to Bacon’s Rebellion.
It
also requires the idea that no substantial notions of the universal,
natural equality of all men was forthcoming from England in the
early-mid 17th century and that American democratic impulses were
largely formed against
English colonial status. However, the colonial venture to North
America was already a product of burgeoning hopes for free expression
of religious minorities who would themselves become an essential part
of the English Revolution from 1642-1651. That
revolution would itself produce radical moments such as the Diggers
and Levellers, who, to quote Wikipedia, “were
a political movement during the English Civil War (1642–1651) that
emphasised popular sovereignty, extended suffrage, equality before
the law, and religious
tolerance, all of which were expressed in the manifesto "Agreement
of the People".” While I am not aware of specific historical
research about the political backgrounds of those coming to the
American colonies to the end of the English Civil War, it would not
be surprising if a few people fleeing persecution and debtors prison
in England might have been Diggers and Levellers or inspired by them,
but most certainly with notions of personal liberty that would extend
among the American colonialists.
In
fact, as John Clegg has noted in an as-yet-unpublished paper, the
distinctions between Africans and Englishmen no doubt began to
develop when they did exactly because there was a history of struggle
between Englishmen of different classes in which the English laborers
and yeomanry had, even as they were being turned into a property-less
working class, established for themselves certain rights and
expectations as custom. Africans held no such history, no such
fought-over rights and claims, and were thus eventually more easily
turned from “not Englishmen” into “not men”, lacking
themselves claims to English citizenship and the rights thus due.
Thus
the idea that a notion of systemic racism and with it the ideology of
race and the practice of racecraft only came into being with the
suspending of the contradiction between American revolutionary
idealism and American slavery strikes me as unsupportable. Allen’s
own points regarding the religio-racial oppression of the Irish
further addresses Field’s earlier complaint of the absence of such
a point.
And
yet there is a subtlety to Fields’ argument utterly lacking in
Allen’s. The idea of a conscious system of social control is
actually unsupportable on a number of grounds, not the least being
the idea that there was in the American colonies a ruling class of
unified opinion. I believe Fields is moving in the right direction,
but cannot grasp the essential move of the production of non-citizens
within the state, which relates to the production of Nation as a
valid identity, but not race. In fact, nation and nationalism have
been even more murderous and criminal than race in the last few
hundred years by quite a bit. If in the name of race, tens of
millions have been oppressed and killed, in the name of nation,
billions have been oppressed and hundreds of millions killed. There
is no ground from which to counterpoise race and nation and in fact
one would be more correct to say that without race there is no
American nation. Instead of taking up the complicated interplay of
racism and nationalism, of the production of race and nation, these
brutal fictions, Fields’ settles for Nation over Race.
It
is hard to say if this is from a prior set of essentially unspoken
political commitments, such as to something like the CPUSA theses on
The Black National Question, or if it is a part of the working out of
her philosophical underpinnings through Emile Durkheim. There is a
further critique of Durkheim to be made and it is unclear to me if
Fields is committed to a Durkheimian sociology or if she simply finds
him engaging in thinking through the problem of race. After all, as
she herself notes, Durkheim deifies, or as she says, divinizes
[citation]
society and for Durkheim, nation is society. The philosopher Gillian
rose critiques Durkheim’s move as one which he grants validity to
Society, but cannot grasp why this society has these particular
values, that is, he sacrifices a comprehension of values in exchange
for the validity of society over values as such, the opposite of the
classic Weberian move in which the values we hold to are
comprehended, but their validity is ultimately uncertain.
One
wonders if there is something important to this point, which treats
racism somewhat individualistically: “Disguised as race, racism
becomes something Afro-Americans are, rather than something racists
do.” [Fields, Barbara J.. Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in
American Life (pp. 96-97). Verso Books. Kindle Edition.] It seems to
take the structural and systemic element out of race and again
replace it with a voluntaristic notion of practice.
There
is something in the defense of nation as valid identity, and thus
identity as somewhat unproblematic, requiring only the distinction
between actual identity and fake identity, that is not worked out in
her work. That this functions as a naturalization of Nation and thus
of the bourgeois nation-state ought to seem odd. In fact, Fields is,
to the best of my knowledge, an opponent of so-called Black
Nationalism, but so was the CPUSA. That is, from the perspective of
the Communist Party, nationalists were incapable of realizing the
Black Nation because the Black nation was a necessary liberatory
moment in the proletarian revolution. Nationalist parties were
incapable of truly serving the Nation, pace
Lenin’s Imperialism
and his later theses on national liberation.
Again, I have no idea if Fields herself has any relationship to or
interest in the CPUSA on these matters, but the logic of her argument
seems to me to make so much more sense if the CPUSA’s theses on the
Black Nation are are a part of her inheritance.
Where
does this leave us? If the fundamental thesis of Fields’ work is
to be cashed out, then the critique of race cannot rest on 1) an
American Exceptionalism both in the production of racism and race and
in democratic values, 2) a mere contradiction between democracy and a
natural rights notion of universal individual liberty on the one hand
and slavery on the other, and 3) a distinction between a valid
National identity that is real (like the Brooklyn bridge) against an
identity that isn’t one (race), that is, a missing critique of
nation in particular and identity in general.
ADDENDUM:
Silvia Federici, in Caliban and the Witch, actually seems to have a view of the dynamic underlying the production of race and gender very similar to that of Barbara and Karen Fields: "Indeed, the political lesson we can learn... is that capitalism... is necessarily committed to racism and sexism. For capitalism must justify and mystify the contradictions built into social relations - the promise of freedom vs. the reality of widespread coercion, and promise of prosperity vs. the reality of widespread poverty...".
Silvia Federici, in Caliban and the Witch, actually seems to have a view of the dynamic underlying the production of race and gender very similar to that of Barbara and Karen Fields: "Indeed, the political lesson we can learn... is that capitalism... is necessarily committed to racism and sexism. For capitalism must justify and mystify the contradictions built into social relations - the promise of freedom vs. the reality of widespread coercion, and promise of prosperity vs. the reality of widespread poverty...".
________________________________________________________________________________
iI
am going to explicitly dodge the argument over structure and agency
here, not because it is not important and not because I do not have
a definite point of view on the matter, but because it will take us
rather far afield.
iiHere
too, it would be going a bit too deep to explicate the notion of
what is constitutive and what is constituting beyond saying that
what is constituted at one moment becomes constituting at another
moment.
iiiIn
fact, she comes very close to this when she says that “and
slavery, rather than something slaves were, became something
slaveholders did—to the corruption of themselves, the injustice of
the slaves, and the probable destruction of the country.” Fields,
Barbara J.. Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life (p.
99). Verso Books. Kindle Edition. Slavery, after all, was
racialized and racializing, but it was ultimately a form of
organization of labor for exploitation and thus a relation between
classes, enslaved laborers and a group of capitalist
slaveholders. But a problem arises insofar as capitalism is not
merely something capitalists do and neither the working class nor the slave class merely merely
something done by capitalists.
ivI
add the “though not uniquely” because I am not aware of her
views on gender or sexuality, she only counterpoises race to Nation
and to bridges.
vIn
the beginning of “Rogues and Geldings”, Fields makes this clear:
““Race” too often recommends itself as a guiltless word, a
neutral term for an empirical fact. It is not. Race appears to be a
neutral description of reality because of the race-racism evasion,
through which immoral acts of discrimination disappear, and then
reappear camouflaged as the victim’s alleged difference.”
Racecraft might best be understood as the evasion itself, the
activity of transforming racism into race. Fields, Barbara J..
Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life (p. 95). Verso
Books. Kindle Edition.
vi
FN
35, https://memory.loc.gov/ammem/awhhtml/awlaw3/slavery.html
“Three indentured servants—John Punch, James Gregory, and Victor
—ran away and were recaptured. James Gregory and Victor, both
white, were given “thirty stripes” and an additional four years
of servitude, whereas John Punch, a Negro, was sentenced to serve
the remainder of his life. Helen Tunnicliff Catterall, ed., Judicial
Cases Concerning American Slavery and the Negro, 5
vols. (1926; reprint, New York: Octagon Books, 1968; KF4545.S5 C3
1968), 1:77”
viihttps://memory.loc.gov/ammem/awhhtml/awlaw3/slavery.html
including fn 36-38 citing the Virginia laws.
No comments:
Post a Comment